Showing posts with label brain. Show all posts
Showing posts with label brain. Show all posts

Wednesday, September 28, 2011

Kant's Intuitions, the intentional stance, and reverse-engineering the mind


“Thoughts without content are empty, intuitions without concepts are blind. The understanding can intuit nothing, the senses can think nothing. Only through their unison can knowledge arise.” -- Immanuel Kant

“We live in a world that is subjectively open. And we are designed by evolution to be "informavores", epistemically hungry seekers of information, in an endless quest to improve our purchase on the world, the better to make decisions about our subjectively open future.” -- Daniel Dennett

"For scientists studying how humans cometo understand their world, the central challenge is this: How do our minds get so much from so little? We build rich causal models,make strong generalizations, and construct powerful abstractions, whereas the input data are sparse, noisy, and ambiguous—in every way far too limited. A massive mismatch looms between the information coming in through our senses and the outputs of cognition." -- Josh Tenenbaum

Organizing by space (space, time, and physics)
There are two faculties of understanding which it is unlikely we have acquired from experience.  The first is that of understanding objects as extended bodies in a 3D space and thus occupying some volume.  I believe it is Kant argued best against the hardcore British Empiricists, who proclaimed that experience is the sole originator of knowledge.  Experiences are the pen strokes, which fill the Empricisit’s tabula rasa.  Kant argued (against Hume) that the concept of a spatially extended object is not acquired from experience – the very notion of experience requires that we already possess the notion of an object in order to have a meaningful percept.  It is as if the Empiricists failed to acknowledge that to make strokes on a sheet of paper, we need to already have a pen.  Kant’s intuitions are the pens of experience.  The requirement of having suitable intuitions for grouping percepts into experiences is what Kant described as a form of transcendental idealism.  “Objectness” is a faculty of human understanding, not something acquired from experience.  If you are a vision researcher, being aware of this can have drastic implications on your research programme.

It has also been argued that there are some primitive notions of object dynamics, aka folk-physics, which can are possessed by very young children.  Given the uniformity of human experience (at least I have no ostensible reason to double that my colleague’s experiences significantly differ from my own), and the diversity in our individual upbringing, it is also unlikely that folk-physics is learned from experience.  However, I don't want to make any strong claims regarding folk-physics.  I feel safe to say that Quantum Mechanics is another story -- it requires years of mathematics and thousands hours of deliberate problem solving to grasp.

Organizing by mind (psychology, mind, and intent)
The second faculty of understanding, which can be found in many aspects of human intelligence, is that of understanding the world in terms of cognitive agents.  Humans have an amazing capability when it comes to attributing stuff with having a mind.  This way of thinking about the world is so common and uniform among children all over the world, that the differences in their upbringing cannot be reconciled with the uniformity of their capability to project humanness onto objects.  Consider the following video (thanks J. Tenenbaum's videos/lectures for pointing this out).


We cannot just view this video os triangles, dots, and lines.  Each one of understands the story in terms of a narrative based on agents and their intent.  We are stimulated by the external world, we take as input sense-data, and the brain helps us make sense of it -- it turns the hodgepodge of data into experience.  But the brain is a mold, it conforms percepts to some shape defined by the mold.  These molds are the faculties of understanding which let us understand things, it is like the faculties of understanding are basis vectors onto which we project all input sense data.  The data is weak and noisy, the priors are strong, and understanding is the result of their union.  An experience without a proper basis is blind, it is just a ball of percepts.  These faculties allow us to have experience.  The experiences, coupled with memory, allow us to obtain understanding – where understanding is the relationship between a given experience and past experiences, either in the form of direct associations between currently-experienced-objects and previously-experienced-objects, or rules abstracted away from previously-experienced-objects being directly applied to the current sense data.

What I am talking about is what philosopher Daniel Dennett refers to by the “intentional stance.”  Given my background in AI and philosophy of mind, it is very likely that Dennett and I have had the same influences.  I like to juxtapose my ideas with those of the classical philosophers such as Descartes, Locke, Kant, Wittgenstein and Pinker -- I’m not sure how Dennett motivates his philosophy nor do I know against whose ideas he juxtaposes his own stance.



At MIT, J. Tenenbaum is pushing these ideas to the next level.  I only wish there was more perception in his work -- toy worlds just don't do it for me.  I want to build intelligent machines, and really cannot afford to sidestep the issue of perception.  Here is a great talk by Josh Tenenbaum on reverse engineering the mind from NIPS 2010. Video is on videolectures.net, just click the link.


Implications for Artificial Intelligence and Machine Vision
Following Josh Tenenbaum, I think that a criticism of classical machine learning is long overdue.  Machine Learning, as a field, has been spewing out hardcore empiricists.  “Let me download your features, my machine learning algorithm will take care of the rest,” they say.  It is like the glory is in the mathematics, which manipulates N-D vectors.  But I argue that intelligence isn’t “in the calculus,” it is what the primitives in the calculus actually represent.  As an undergraduate I proclaimed, “I am not a mathematician, I am a physicists.  I care about the structure of the world, not the structure of proofs. “  As a graduate student I proclaimed, “The glory isn’t in the manipulation of vectors, the glory is understanding the what/why of encoding information about the world into vectors.  I am a computer vision researcher, not a machine learning researcher.”  That is why the view of the world as coming from K different classes is wrong – this is merely a convenient view if the statistician’s toolbox is at your disposal.  It is all about structuring the input to match a researcher’s high-level intuitions about the world. 

Monday, March 30, 2009

Time Travel, Perception, and Mind-wandering

Today's post is dedicated to ideas promulgated by Bar's most recent article, "The proactive brain: memory for predictions."

Bar builds on the foundation of his former thesis, namely that the brain's 'default' mode of operation is to daydream, fantasize, and continuously revisit and reshape past memories and experiences. While it makes sense that traversing the internal network of past experiences is useful when trying to understand a complex novel phenomenon, why exert so much work when just 'chilling out' a.k.a. being in the 'default' mode? Bar's proposal is that this seemingly wasteful daydreaming is actually crucial for generating virtual experiences and synthesizing not-directly-experienced, yet critically useful memories of alternate scenarios. These 'alternate future memories' are how our brain recombines tidbits from actual experiences and helps us understand novel scenarios before they actually happen. It makes sense that the brain has a method for 'densifying' the network of past experiences, but that this happens in the 'default' mode a truly bold view held by Bar.

In the domain of visual perception and scene understanding, the world has much regularity. Thus the predictions generated by our brain often match the percept, and thus accurate predictions rid us of the need to exert mental brainpower on certain predictable aspects of the world. For example, seeing a bunch of cars on a road along with a bunch of windows on a building pre-sensitizes us so much with respect to seeing a stop sign in an intimate spatial relationship with the other objects that we don't need to perceive much more than speckle of red for a nanosecond to confirm its presence in the scene.

Quoting Bar, "we are rarely in the 'now'" since when understanding the visual world we integrate information from multiple points in time. We use the information perceptible to our senses (the now), memories of former experiences (the past), as well all of the recombined and synthesized scenarios explored by our brains and encoded as virtual memories (plausible futures). In each moment of our waking life, our brains provide us with a shortlist of primed (to be expected) objects, contexts, and their configurations related to our immediate perceptible future. Who says we can't travel through time? -- it seems we are already living a few seconds ahead of direct perception (the immediate now).